Scientists Are Working Towards a Unified Theory of Consciousness


The origin of consciousness has teased the minds of philosophers and scientists for centuries. In the last decade, neuroscientists have begun to piece together its neural underpinningsā€”that is, how the brain, through its intricate connections, transforms electrical signaling between neurons into consciousness.

Yet the field is fragmented, an international team of neuroscientists recently wrote in a new paper in Neuron. Many theories of consciousness contradict each other, with different ideas about where and how consciousness emerges in the brain.

Some theories are even duking it out in a mano-a-mano test by imaging the brains of volunteers as they perform different tasks in clinical test centers across the globe.

But unlocking the neural basis of consciousness doesnā€™t have to be confrontational. Rather, theories can be integrated, wrote the authors, who were part of the Human Brain Projectā€”a massive European endeavor to map and understand the brainā€”and specialize in decoding brain signals related to consciousness.

Not all authors agree on the specific brain mechanisms that allow us to perceive the outer world and construct an inner world of ā€œself.ā€ But by collaborating, they merged their ideas, showing that different theories arenā€™t necessarily mutually incompatibleā€”in fact, they could be consolidated into a general framework of consciousness and even inspire new ideas that help unravel one of the brainā€™s greatest mysteries.

If successful, the joint mission could extend beyond our own noggins. Brain organoids, or ā€œmini-brains,ā€ that roughly mimic early human development are becoming increasingly sophisticated, spurring ethical concerns about their potential for developing self-awareness (to be clear, there arenā€™t any signs). Meanwhile, similar questions have been raised about AI. A general theory of consciousness, based on the human mind, could potentially help us evaluate these artificial constructs.

ā€œIs it realistic to reconcile theories, or even aspire to a unified theory of consciousness?ā€ the authors asked. ā€œWe take the standpoint that the existence of multiple theories is a sign of healthiness in this nascent fieldā€¦such that multiple theories can simultaneously contribute to our understanding.ā€

Lost in Translation

Iā€™m conscious. You are too. We see, smell, hear, and feel. We have an internal world that tells us what weā€™re experiencing. But the lines get blurry for people in different stages of coma or for those locked-inā€”they can still perceive their surroundings but canā€™t physically respond. We lose consciousness in sleep every night and during anesthesia. Yet, somehow, we regain consciousness. How?

With extensive imaging of the brain, neuroscientists today agree that consciousness emerges from the brainā€™s wiring and activity. But multiple theories argue about how electrical signals in the brain produce rich and intimate experiences of our lives.

Part of the problem, wrote the authors, is that there isnā€™t a clear definition of ā€œconsciousness.ā€ In this paper, they separated the term into two experiences: one outer, one inner. The outer experience, called phenomenal consciousness, is when we immediately realize what weā€™re experiencingā€”for example, seeing a total solar eclipse or the northern lights.

The inner experience is a bit like a ā€œgut feelingā€ in that it helps to form expectations and types of memory, so that tapping into it lets us plan behaviors and actions.

Both are aspects of consciousnesses, but the difference is hardly delineated in previous work. It makes comparing theories difficult, wrote the authors, but thatā€™s what they set out to do.

Meet the Contenders

Using their ā€œtwo experienceā€ framework, they examined five prominent consciousness theories.

The first, the global neuronal workspace theory, pictures the brain as a city of sorts. Each local brain region ā€œhubā€ dynamically interacts with a ā€œglobal workspace,ā€ which integrates and broadcasts information to other hubs for further processingā€”allowing information to reach the consciousness level. In other words, we only perceive something when all pieces of sensory informationā€”sight, hearing, touch, tasteā€”are woven into a temporary neural sketchpad. According to this theory, the seat of consciousness is in the frontal parts of the brain.

The second, integrated information theory, takes a more globalist view. The idea is that consciousness stems from a series of cause-effect reactions from the brainā€™s networks. With the right neural architecture, connections, and network complexity, consciousness naturally emerges. The theory suggests the back of the brain sparks consciousness.

Then thereā€™s dendritic integration theory, the coolest new kid in town. Unlike previous ideas, this theory waved the front or back of the brain goodbye and instead zoomed in on single neurons in the cortex, the outermost part of the brain and a hub for higher cognitive functions such as reasoning and planning.

The cortex has extensive connections to other parts of the brainā€”for example, those that encode memories and emotions. One type of neuron, deep inside the cortex, especially stands out. Physically, these neurons resemble trees with extensive ā€œrootsā€ and ā€œbranches.ā€ The roots connect to other parts of the brain, whereas the upper branches help calculate errors in the neuronā€™s computing. In turn, these upper branches generate an error signal that corrects mistakes through multiple rounds of learning.

The two compartments, while physically connected, go about their own businessā€”turning a single neuron into multiple computers. Hereā€™s the crux: Thereā€™s a theoretical ā€œgateā€ between the upper and lower neural ā€œofficesā€ for each neuron. During consciousness, the gate opens, allowing information to flow between the cortex and other brain regions. In dreamless sleep and other unconscious states, the gate closes.

Like a light switch, this theory suggests that consciousness is supported by flicking individual neuron gates on or off on a grand scale.

The last two theories propose that recurrent processing in the brainā€”that is, it learns from previous experiencesā€”is essential for consciousness. Instead of ā€œexperiencingā€ the world, the brain builds an internal simulation that constantly predicts the ā€œhere and nowā€ to control what we perceive.

A Unified Theory?

All the theories have extensive experiments to back up their claims. So, whoā€™s right? To the authors, the key is to consider consciousness not as a singular concept, but as a ā€œladderā€ of sorts. The brain functions at multiple levels: cells, local networks, brain regions, and finally, the whole brain.

When examining theories of consciousness, it also makes sense to delineate between different levels. For example, the dendritic integration theoryā€”which considers neurons and their connectionsā€”is on the level of single cells and how they contribute to consciousness. It makes the theory ā€œneutral,ā€ in that it can easily fit into ideas at a larger scaleā€”those that mostly rely on neural network connections or across larger brain regions.

Although itā€™s seemingly difficult to reconcile various ideas about consciousness, two principles tie them together, wrote the team. One is that consciousness requires feedback, within local neural circuits and throughout the brain. The other is integration, in that any feedback signals need to be readily incorporated back into neural circuits, so they can change their outputs. Finally, all authors agree that local, short connections are vital but not enough. Long distance connections from the cortex to deeper brain areas are required for consciousness.

So, is an integrated theory of consciousness possible? The authors are optimistic. By defining multiple aspects of consciousnessā€”immediate responses versus internal thoughtsā€”itā€™ll be clearer how to explore and compare results from different experiments. For now, the global neuronal workspace theory mostly focuses on the ā€œinner experienceā€ that leads to consciousness, whereas others try to tackle the ā€œouter experienceā€ā€”what we immediately experience.

For the theories to merge, the latter groups will have to explain how consciousness is used for attention and planning, which are hallmarks for immediate responses. But fundamentally, wrote the authors, they are all based on different aspects of neuronal connections near and far. With more empirical experiments, and as increasingly more sophisticated brain atlases come online, theyā€™ll move the field forward.

Hopefully, the authors write, ā€œan integrated theory of consciousnessā€¦may come within reach within the next years or decades.ā€

Image Credit: SIMON LEE / Unsplash

Latest articles

spot_imgspot_img

Related articles

Leave a reply

Please enter your comment!
Please enter your name here

spot_imgspot_img